Part Two: Deduction vs. induction
The first part
introduced the essence of logics, syllogisms and the concepts of validity and
soundness. It was intended to present a fundamental way of thinking
philosophically about big words such as truth and certainty, and to emphasise
that ‘logical’ does not necessarily mean ‘true’. I would strongly recommend that you read Part One before proceeding.
I know it is a long text, but it is also essential to be familiar with the
concepts that are discussed there.
In Part Two, I
want to take the discussion a step away from general philosophy and closer to
concepts more relevant to science: deductive
and inductive reasoning. These are still fundamental to many, if not all branches
of philosophy, but inductive reasoning in particular is central to the natural
sciences.
Deductive and inductive reasoning are both forms of extrapolation (which was discussed in Part One). Strictly speaking, deduction is the act of reasoning from the general to the particular, while induction is the act of reasoning from the particular to the general. Before you get a headache trying to understand what on Earth that even means, let me talk you through a few simple examples.
Deduction is thinking
that if all bananas are sweet, the banana you are about to eat will taste
sweet. Induction, on the other hand, would be the reverse: if you eat a banana
and find it sweet, you can expect other bananas to be sweet as well. In this
case, ‘the general’ refers to all bananas, and ‘the particular’ is the banana
you have or ate.
So, knowing that
the general (all bananas) has a certain feature or attribute (tasting sweet),
you may deduce that the particular
(the banana in your hand) might possess that attribute as well. Conversely,
observing an attribute (sweet taste) in the particular (the banana you ate) may
lead to the inductive conclusion that
that feature may belong to the general (all bananas).
If you are
observant, you may already be wondering: does induction come before deduction
then? How would you know that all bananas are sweet, unless that is a
conclusion you have reached inductively by tasting many bananas? Well noted –
but do not jump to conclusions! Although that may be true in many cases, there
are many exceptions as well. (Trick quiz: was that inductive or deductive
thinking?)
The main type of
deduction that does not rely on induction is based on definitions. A classical example of something that is true
by definition is that all bachelors are
unmarried men. This is because the word bachelor means unmarried man. Thus, if you meet someone you know is a
bachelor (he may have presented himself as such), you can deduce that he (!) is
an unmarried man. This is not because you have met many bachelors and they have
all turned out to be unmarried men, but because if he is not an unmarried man,
then he is not a bachelor (or… maybe he is lying to you).
You may recall
this example from Part One as the first example of a syllogism. I repeat
it here because it is not only a sound syllogism, but also one that illustrates
deductive reasoning:
P: All bachelors are unmarried men
P: Peter is a bachelor
C: Therefore, Peter is an unmarried man
Here, we go from
the general (all bachelors) to the particular (Peter). We know something about
the general, something that applies to all of them; and from that, we reason
that this something is true also for every particular individual or unit in
this general group. We reason from the
general to the particular in deduction.
Recall that
deduction and induction are inferences,
and as such not necessarily true. Again, what we are concerned about is how
we reason when we infer. We want the reasoning to be valid, so we can
be certain that the deductive or inductive conclusion is as true as the initial
premise. In the above example, the first premise is true by definition, and
therefore unquestionable (the only grey area would be a widower, a man whose
wife has died) – unless you want to challenge the definition, but then it
becomes a matter of language, not the nature of the world. The second premise,
however, may or may not be true. As a result, the conclusion is only as certain
as the second premise. If Peter is not a bachelor, then he is either married or
not a man.
P: All unmarried men are bachelors
P: Peter is a bachelor
C: Therefore, Peter is an unmarried man
Or:
P: All bachelors are unmarried men
P: Peter is an unmarried man
C: Therefore, Peter is a bachelor
And so on…
Both attributes
(being a bachelor and being an unmarried man) are mutually inclusive. But there are deductive syllogisms that
are not true both ways, so to speak. Consider an example:
P: All tall people wear hats
P: Gareth is a tall person
C: Therefore, Gareth wears a hat
This cannot be written as:
P: All tall people wear hats
P: Gareth wears a hat
C: Therefore, Gareth is tall
This is because
the key word is not to be. They are not the same. Think about it. The
first syllogism claims that all tall people wear hats (a ridiculous statement,
perhaps, but let us take it as a true fact for the purpose of this explanation),
but that does not imply what the second syllogism states: that all people that
wear hats necessarily are tall. In contrast, bachelors are unmarried men, and as a consequence unmarried men are also bachelors!
Hopefully, you now
understand the basics of deduction, and recognise that it has important
set-backs (think about how much we actually can use deduction for…). Please
have them in mind, as I will now explain induction, and later go on to compare
deductive and inductive reasoning.
I have been
struggling to formulate the following example of inductive reasoning as a
sensible syllogism, but I think the message can go through as a simple
statement anyway: All swans observed so
far are white; therefore, all swans are probably
white. This is a generalisation based on observations of the particular
(the portion all swans that we have observed), which concludes that the general
(all swans that exist) possesses the same traits (colour) as the particular. We
reason from the particular to the general.
(As a side note, I
might add that this particular example, although classical, becomes problematic
when you think about swanlings, which have a dark grey plumage. For that
inductive claim to be accurate, swanlings must be excluded from the definition
of swans, meaning that sub-adults are not considered members of the species,
which further suggests that infants are not humans, and that abortion must be
ethical… Woah, maybe I should calm down a bit there, hahaha! Actually, that
induction can be improved by specifying that adult swans are white!)
Naturally, you
wonder how we can be sure that all swans are white, when we haven’t seen them
all. How can we know there are not
black, blue or pinkish red swans out there?
Of course, we
cannot know that. We can only be fairly
certain, or guess that it is so.
It is simply a logical impossibility to be absolutely certain about a
(non-defining) attribute of a group without having observed every single member.
However, unless we
have a reason to suspect that there may be deviations from the observed
pattern, we can be quite confident that the pattern will hold even for
situations that we have not observed. Still, that is no guarantee, only a probability.
Induction
reasoning may be regarded as the core of
science. Scientists observe features of the world and then, by working out why these features are the way they are,
try to predict what will happen in a similar situation, or, if their
understanding is deeper, predict what can happen if the situation changes. This
is all based on generalising from a limited number of observations about
unobserved events, groups, things, whatever. These generalisations are then
usually tested by observing more examples of the unobserved things, and if the
generalisations appear true, hooray!
The reason
for relying on induction is simply that we cannot observe the whole world. We simply do not have the time
nor the labour to do it. If we want to say something about what we have not yet
seen, we nearly always have to use inductive reasoning, based on what we have
seen so far.
As long as we are
all aware of the inescapable problem of uncertainty in induction
(deduction may very well be uncertain too, but it is at least possible to be
entirely certain of a deductive statement, while absolute confidence in an
inductive claim is unfeasible), as long as we treat those conclusions with
care, this way of reasoning is amazingly
useful, because it allows us to at least approach a truth about something
unknown. Deductive reasoning is limited to what we already know – mostly what
we know because we defined it that way. We will discuss this more later, in the
main comparison between these two ways of thinking.
However, there is one problematic aspect of induction, one that
causes trouble for all branches of science that deal with predicting the future, or understanding the past (e.g. predicting
natural disasters such as climate change or volcanic eruptions; predicting
evolution and genetic changes, including extinction or survival of species;
calculating how much longer our resources will last, and the implications of
their over-use; and all sorts of things that lie at the heart of what can be
seen as one of the main utilities of science).
To illustrate this
fundamental problem with the inductive way of reasoning, let us consider another
example:
P: The sun has
risen every day since recorded history
P: Tomorrow is a
day
C: Therefore,
the sun will probably rise tomorrow
Intuitively, this
seems correct, but it is actually not
even valid. To make this reasoning valid, we must assume that the world
will work the same way tomorrow that it did today and has in the observed past.
In other words, we need to assume that
the universe works in a consistent
manner.
That is a very
intuitive claim, since it seems silly to think otherwise: we have little or no
evidence to suggest that the world will function differently tomorrow, or any
time in the foreseeable future. In the same way, it is against common sense to
think that the universal laws of nature were different in a time before our
own. Scientific evidence suggests that there was a time when there was no sun,
and a time when there was a sun but no Earth. Scientists use other evidence to
predict that the sun will collapse one day, if it runs out of ‘fuel’. Hence the
word ‘probably’ in the conclusion: it safeguards against the chance that the
specific example might change.
Still, what we
assume must assume in order to call inductive syllogisms of that nature valid,
is that the fundamental laws of the universe – the laws about how things exist
and behave – have always been the same, and forever will be. We can accept that
particular examples may be different, but the underlying thought is that the
basic features of the universe are constant. (I am implying that the sun and
Earth are not basic features of the universe.)
But, the problem
is, can we really justify that assumption? Based only on what we have seen in
the past and present, can we justify the
claim that the sun is more likely to rise than not? The painful problem is
that the assumption that ‘what has happened every day until now is likely to
happen tomorrow as well’ can only be justified if we assume that ‘the world
always has and always will work the same way’, which is the very thing we want to show with the first assumption. Thus, we
have one assumption that only can be justified by another assumption, which in
turn is only justifiable by accepting the first assumption. This circular
reasoning is a big bad fallacy, as you may recall from Part One.
I quote a handout
from philosophy class:
If nature is uniform and regular in its
behaviour, then events in the observed
past and present are a sure guide to unobserved events in the unobserved past, present and future. But
the only grounds for believing that nature is uniform are the observed events in the past and present.
We can’t seem to go beyond the events we observe without assuming the very
thing we need to prove – that is, that unobserved parts of the world operate in
the same way as the parts we’ve observed.
This is the
problem with attempting to extrapolate inductively about the past or future: the
necessary assumption cannot be logically justified. Although it seems
intuitive, it is actually a fallacy.
Another reason to
question the validity of the assumption of the universal laws being constant
across time is that scientists also seem to hold the belief that everything is constantly changing.
Unless they mean ‘everything except the
universal laws is constantly changing’, we are looking at a troublesome inconsistency here (inconsistency, in
the philosophical sense, is holding
beliefs that contradict one another). The universe cannot be the same and, at the
same time, change, since remaining the same is the same thing as not
changing, by definition. One of those beliefs must be discarded (except if the
constancy solely refers to the universal laws, and the change refers to
everything else), which is tricky since both ideas are rather intuitive. We see
things changing with time every day, every week, every month, etc. But we also
see that many things stay the same.
Still, even though
there are logical reasons for doubt, things that science has accomplished,
using those very methods, seem (!) to have hit something right somehow.
Although the reasoning seems limping, it appears to have reached the goal.
Either, the assumption that the world works in a consistent way just happens to be true (note that
circular reasoning does not imply falseness: that an argument is circular only
means that is cannot be shown to be true or false, but it has no
bearing on whether it is actually true or false – it is either true or false or
somewhere in between, but it cannot be demonstrated logically, and is therefore
not good reasoning, even though it might be correct, just by luck!), or it is almost true, or it simply does not
matter whether it is true or not, and the logical analysis of the flaws of the method
is wrong somewhere.
In Notes from Underground, Fyodor
Dostoyevsky writes that “man has such a predilection for systems and abstract
deductions that he is ready to distort the truth intentionally, he is ready to
deny the evidence of his senses only to justify his logic”. I interpret it to
be questioning the assumption (really) that our logic has anything to the
natural world. How can we know that logics really describes how the world
works, and not just the way we humans think? This is a
really interesting topic, one which I hope we will come back to later.
But, now I think it is about time we get on with comparing deduction and
induction.
In general, it can
be said that deduction is more certain
but less informative, while induction is less certain but more informative.
(Or, really, one should say that deduction has greater potential of preserving the certainty of its
premises, while a great deal of certainty may be lost through inductive
generalisation.)
This is really
because of the nature of these ways of reasoning. When you argue from the
general to the specific, you just apply what you know about a group to a
particular member of that group. If I know that most rocks are hard, I can be
fairly sure that if I touch a rock, it will feel hard. In contrast, when you
argue from the specific to the general, you are dealing with the uncertainty of
whether the feature you are reasoning about applies to the whole group or not.
In deduction, you know it applies
throughout the group, and can therefore be confident that any particular member
will also possess that feature; but, in induction, you cannot be sure that the
feature is something that applies to the whole group based on only one or a few
particular examples. Although many rocks are grey, it happens to be that colour
is not consistent among rocks – there are many rocks that are red, white,
beige, green, black, etc., and many have multiple colours!
But, I hope you
realise that you cannot reason deductively without knowing anything about the
whole group! Therefore, deduction is really not very informative at all.
Deduction can only tell you things about particular examples from a broader
category of which you already have a lot of information, and the information
you apply to these particular examples is already known. Deduction is a way of
inferring information from broad category to a narrow part of that or a similar
category, rather than discovering new information. It is a tool of inference,
not investigation. Deduction is nearly useless in the face of an unknown group
of things.
Induction is the
method of choice when you want to learn about something new. By making
(careful) generalisations about the whole group from a limited sample, it
provides a platform for beginning to
study this group. These generalisations are usually checked by observing
additional examples from the category, and, if the generalisations seem to
hold, you keep looking for more particular examples; if you find that there are
too many exceptions to your generalisation, you should reconsider or discard
that idea and start over, drawing new generalisations from the examples you
have now studied. (This systematic approach is not part of the essence of
induction, but rather the way it is used effectively in science to learn about
the unknown.)
While induction
makes it possible to explore, deduction cannot do much more than point.
(But, note well
that induction does not allow us to explore completely
unknown situations. We always need at least one example of the particular
to make generalised or inductive statements. When faced with the complete
absence of specific examples, loose inference based on educated guesswork is
probably the best we could do. Ideally, these guesses should assume the same
predicting nature of inductive generalisations: the guesses should encourage
explorers to test the ideas, by finding examples of that unknown, and comparing
the guesses with observations.)
As already
mentioned before, deduction is often
preceded by inductive investigations. Since deduction can only preserve certainty, never increase it,
it follows that deductive conclusions made from inductive premises is only as
certain as those inductive claims. This is a practical limitation of deduction.
However, induction
alone does not take us far. It can help us learn about a category of entities
in the world, but that is where it stops. Deduction
is one way of making use of information gained from induction, by allowing
us to apply the general knowledge to specific situations. If we have observed
the consequences of earthquakes and learned about it through induction, we can put
this general information to use by applying it deductively on earthquakes we
experience now, and better know what to do when they occur and how to act after
they have passed.
In other words,
deduction and induction seem to come hand in hand, combined, in practice,
although they are each others’ opposites, theoretically.
The final point I
want to make in this comparison is about the role of language in deduction and induction. In one (philosophical)
sense, language is based on inductive generalisations: we implicitly organise the
world into general categories by putting names on them, based on common
characteristics. We notice that some things have much in common with each
other, but still are different from everything else, and call them something
unique, e.g. dog, table, teacher. Dogs bark, but neither do tables, teachers or
anything else, tables have a specific shape and function that make them tables,
etc.
We also implicitly
use deductive reasoning by expecting similar behaviour from members of the same
‘thing, which may be distinct from other ‘things’. For example, if you punch a
dog, it will probably feel pain, and maybe bite you; if you punch a table, the
table might take damage, but will not react, and you will surely hurt yourself;
if you punch a teacher, you are in big trouble.
In that sense, by
using language, you are implicitly also using deductive and inductive
reasoning, often combined.
What is more
important, however, is that deduction and induction effectively depend on that the world is organisable into
discrete categories, i.e. things/words. What I am trying to argue is that
language is not only a way of communicating ideas; language is also a way of organising the world into discrete categories,
thus making deductive and inductive logics possible. Deduction is the art of
reasoning from such categories to their specific members, and induction is the
art of reasoning from specific members to broader categories. If the world is
not organisable into discrete groups, such reasoning falls apart.
That is the main
reason why many modern taxonomists (scientists who classify living organisms)
are struggling with distinguishing different species. The more the biologists
learn about the diversity of living organisms, the more they realise that the
concept of a ‘species’ is more a made-up grouping than a real, natural unit.
There is so much continuous variation within and between ‘species’ that the
scientist must make rather arbitrary decisions on how to decide the ‘limit’
between closely related ‘species’. This is just one example of humans trying to
impose order on something that apparently is not meant to be organisable.
I admit that this
discussion might have been rather confusing, but I hope at least the general
message has come across. Scientific research is based mainly on inductive
reasoning, or generalisations, basically; scientific inference, on the other
hand, relies on deduction, the opposite of induction. Deduction is the art of
inferring from the general to the particular, while induction is about generalising
from the particular to the general. Induction is less certain that deduction,
but much more useful when it comes to investigating the world. Both are often
used in combination, however, as they are not very meaningful in isolation.
No comments:
Post a Comment